Curs de Limba Engleza Pentru Stiinte Politice

download Curs de Limba Engleza Pentru Stiinte Politice

of 116

description

Curs de Limba Engleza Pentru Stiinte Politice

Transcript of Curs de Limba Engleza Pentru Stiinte Politice

  • 1

    SUPORT DE CURS

    LIMBA ENGLEZ pentru

    TIINE POLITICE

  • 2

    Materialul de mai jos este destinat cursului de limba englez pentru studenii facultii de

    tiine Politice. Materialul nu reprezint un curs de limba englez, ci un course pack

    (sau suport de curs) destinat studenilor amintii. Acesta este compus dintr-un numr de

    texte teoretice de profil, complementate pe alocuri de scurte indicaii i explicaii i

    nsoite de un numr de ntrebri i exerciii de traducere. Materialul este gndit astfel

    nct (a) s familiarizeze studenii cu termenii de specialitate din domeniile de profil; (b)

    s i obinuiasc pe acetia cu lectura unor texte de specialitate din domeniile amintite;

    (c) s le ofere studenilor ocazia de a utiliza n discuii conceptele deprinse. Cu puin

    ans, suportul de curs se poate dovedi i o experien util n raport cu alte cursuri

    urmate de studenii departamentului de tiine Politice.

    Materialul presupune o cunoatere adecvat a limbii engleze, care s permit

    parcurgerea textelor (fie i cu ajutorul unui dicionar), nelegerea i rezolvarea

    ntrebrilor i traducerea fragmentelor indicate. Presupune, de asemenea, i o minim

    familiaritate cu filozofia politic sau tiinele politice. Pentru a primi o not final pe baza

    suportului de curs, studenii trebuie s (a) participe la examenul final; (b) s prezinte un

    caiet de exerciii care s conin rezolvrile ntrebrilor i exerciiilor de la cel puin trei

    din cele ase teme/subteme din suportul de curs; (c) s prezinte o lucrare de minimum

    2500 cuvinte pe oricare dintre temele/subtemele amintite.

  • 3

    Contents

    A. CONCEPTS IN POLITICAL THOUGHT .................................................................... 4 I. COSMOPOLITANISM VS. PATRIOTISM................................................................ 4

    Martha Nussbaum David Held Michael Walzer Alasdair MacIntyre Richard Rorty

    Maurizio Viroli

    II. POLITICAL LIBERALISM..................................................................................... 20

    Thomas Jefferson Richard Rorty John Tomasi John Rawls

    III. MODELS OF DEMOCRACY................................................................................ 32

    Montesquieu James Madison Robert Dahl James Fishkin Anthony King

    Benjamin Barber Andrew Shapiro Cass Sunstein

    IV. FREEDOM OF SPEECH AND ACADEMIC FREEDOM ................................... 55

    John Milton John Stuart Mill Louis Brandeis Raymond Allen Ronald Dworkin

    Dinesh DSouza Catharine MacKinnon

    B. THE AMERICAN CONSTITUTION.......................................................................... 75

    Short introduction Text Issue for discussion

    C. GLOBALIZATION...................................................................................................... 92

    Anthony Giddens Robert Gilpin Timothy Taylor John Gray Thomas Friedman

    Robert Kaplan David Held

  • 4

    A. CONCEPTS IN POLITICAL THOUGHT

    I. COSMOPOLITANISM VS. PATRIOTISM

    The dialogue between cosmopolitanism and patriotism below is introduced by Martha

    Nussbaums plea in favor of the former (and against the latter). She is joined by David

    Held, who defines the main characteristics of the cultural cosmopolitanism he

    advocates; and taken to task by Michael Walzer, who seems to argue that he does not

    know what to do with the notion of cosmopolitan citizenship.

    Alasdair MacIntyre provides a definition of patriotism, which distinguishes it

    from apparently similar attitudes, and likens it to other, apparently less similar ones.

    Another supporter of patriotism, Richard Rorty, advances two different definitions of the

    political community which might help us distinguish between the philosophical

    underpinnings of the cosmopolitan and the patriotic stances. Finally, Maurizio Viroli is

    careful to differentiate patriotism from nationalism.

  • 5

    I.1 Martha Nussbaum, Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism

    (excerpted from Martha Nussbaum, Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism, Boston Review,

    Vol. 19, No. 5, 1994)

    [Tagores novel] The Home and the World is a tragic story of the defeat of a

    reasonable and principled cosmopolitanism by the forces of nationalism and

    ethnocentrism. I believe that Tagore sees deeply when he sees that at bottom nationalism

    and ethnocentric particularism are not alien to one another, but akin that to give support

    to nationalist sentiments subverts, ultimately, even the values that hold a nation together,

    because it substitutes a colorful idol for the substantive universal values of justice and

    right. Once one has said, I am an Indian first, a citizen of the world second, once one

    has made that morally questionable move of self-definition by a morally irrelevant

    characteristic, then what, indeed, will stop one from saying, as Tagores characters so

    quickly learn to say, I am a Hindu first, and an Indian second, I am an upper-caste

    landlord first, and a Hindu second. Only the cosmopolitan stance so boringly flat

    has the promise of transcending these divisions, because only this stance asks us to give

    our first allegiance to what is morally good and that which, being good, I can commend

    as such to all human beings.

    Proponents of nationalism in politics and in education frequently make a thin

    concession to cosmopolitanism. They may argue, for example, that although nations

    should in general base education and political deliberation on shared national values, a

    commitment to basic human rights should be part of any national educational system, and

    that this commitment will in a sense serve to hold many nations together. This seems to

    be a fair comment on practical reality; and the emphasis on human rights is certainly

    necessary for a world in which nations interact all the time on terms, let us hope, of

    justice and mutual respect.

    But is it sufficient? As students here grow up, is it sufficient for them to learn that

    they are above all citizens of the United States, but that they ought to respect the basic

    human rights of citizens of India, Bolivia, Nigeria, and Norway? Or should they, as I

    think in addition to giving special attention to the history and current situation of their

  • 6

    own nation learn a good deal more than is frequently the case about the rest of the

    world in which they live, about India and Bolivia and Nigeria and Norway and their

    histories, problems, and comparative successes? Should they learn only that citizens of

    India have equal basic human rights, or should they also learn about the problems of

    hunger and pollution in India, and the implications of these problems for larger problems

    of global hunger and global ecology? Most important, should they be taught that they are

    above all citizens of the United States, or should they instead be taught that they are

    above all citizens of a world of human beings, and that, while they themselves happen to

    be situated in the United States, they have to share this world of human beings with the

    citizens of other countries?

    Asked where he came from, the ancient Greek Cynic philosopher Diogenes

    replied, I am a citizen of the world. He meant by this, it appears, that he refused to be

    defined by his local origins and local group memberships, so central to the self-image of

    a conventional Greek male; he insisted on defining himself in terms of more universal

    aspirations and concerns. The Stoics who followed his lead developed his image of the

    kosmou polits or world citizen more fully, arguing that each of us dwells, in effect, in

    two communities the local community of our birth, and the community of human

    argument and aspiration that is truly great and truly common, in which we look neither

    to this corner nor to that, but measure the boundaries of our nation by the sun (Seneca,

    De Otio). It is this community that is, most fundamentally, the source of our moral

    obligations. With respect to the most basic moral values such as justice, we should

    regard all human beings as our fellow citizens and neighbors (Plutarch, On the Fortunes

    of Alexander). We should regard our deliberations as, first and foremost, deliberations

    about human problems of people in particular concrete situations, not problems growing

    out of a national identity that is altogether unlike that of others. Diogenes knew that the

    invitation to think as a world citizen was, in a sense, an invitation to be an exile from the

    comfort of patriotism and its easy sentiments, to see our own ways of life from the point

    of view of justice and the good. The accident of where one is born is just that, an

    accident; any human being might have been born in any nation. Recognizing this, his

    Stoic successors held, we should not allow differences of nationality or class or ethnic

    membership or even gender to erect barriers between us and our fellow human beings.

  • 7

    We should recognize humanity wherever it occurs, and give its fundamental ingredients,

    reason and moral capacity, our first allegiance and respect.

    Boston Review

  • 8

    I.2 David Held, National Culture, the Globalization of Communications and the

    Bounded Political Community

    (excerpted from David Held, National Culture, the Globalization of Communications

    and the Bounded Political Community, Logos, Vol. 1, No. 3, Summer 2002)

    Cultural cosmopolitanism is not at loggerheads with national culture; it does not deny

    cultural difference or the enduring significance of national tradition. It is not against

    cultural diversity. Few, if any, contemporary cosmopolitans hold such views Rather,

    cultural cosmopolitanism should be understood as the capacity to mediate between

    national cultures, communities of fate and alternative styles of life. It encompasses the

    possibility of dialogue with the traditions and discourses of others with the aim of

    expanding the horizons of ones own framework of meaning and prejudice. Political

    agents who can reason from the point of view of others are better equipped to resolve,

    and resolve fairly, the challenging transboundary issues that create overlapping

    communities of fate. The development of this kind of cultural cosmopolitanism depends

    on the recognition by growing numbers of peoples of the increasing interconnectedness

    of political communities in diverse domains, and the development of an understanding of

    overlapping collective fortunes which require collective solutions locally, nationally,

    regionally and globally.

    Cultural cosmopolitanism emphasizes the possible fluidity of individual identity

    peoples remarkable capacity to forge new identities using materials from diverse

    cultural sources, and to flourish while so doing. It celebrates, as Rushdie put it,

    hybridity, impurity, intermingling, the transformation that comes of new and unexpected

    combinations of human beings, cultures, ideas, politics, movies, songs. But it is the

    ability to stand outside of a singular location (the location of ones birth, land,

    upbringing, conversion), and to mediate traditions, that lies at its core. However, there are

    no guarantees about the extent to which such an outlook will prevail. For it has to survive

    and jostle for recognition alongside deeply held national, ethnic and religious traditions.

    It is a cultural and cognitive orientation, not an inevitability of history.

    The core requirements of cultural cosmopolitanism include:

  • 9

    Recognition of the increasing interconnectedness of political communities in

    diverse domains including the social, economic and environmental;

    Development of an understanding of overlapping collective fortunes which

    require collective solutions locally, nationally, regionally and globally;

    The celebration of difference, diversity and hybridity while learning how to

    reason from the point of view of others and mediate traditions.

    Like national culture, cultural cosmopolitanism is a cultural project, but with one

    difference: it is better adapted and suited to our regional and global age.

    Logos

  • 10

    I.3 Alasdair MacIntyre, Is Patriotism a Virtue?

    (excerpted from Alasdair MacIntyre, Is Patriotism a Virtue?, in Ronald Beiner, ed.,

    Theorizing Citizenship, Albany: State University of New York Press, 1995)

    A necessary first step in the direction of any clarification is to distinguish patriotism

    properly so-called from two other sets of attitudes that are all too easily assimilated to it.

    The first is that exhibited by those who are protagonists of their own nations causes

    because and only because, so they assert, it is their nation which is the champion of some

    great moral ideal. What distinguishes their attitude from patriotism is twofold: first it

    is the ideal and not the nation which is the primary object of their regard; and secondly

    insofar as their regard for the ideal provides good reasons for allegiance to their country,

    it provides good reasons for anyone at all to uphold their countrys cause, irrespective of

    their nationality or citizenship.

    Patriotism by contrast is defined in terms of a kind of loyalty to a particular nation

    which only those possessing that particular nationality can exhibit. Only Frenchmen can

    be patriotic about France, while anyone can make the cause of civilisation their own. But

    it would be all too easy in noticing this to fail to make a second equally important

    distinction. Patriotism is not to be confused with a mindless loyalty to ones own

    particular nation which has no regard at all for the characteristics of that particular nation.

    Patriotism does generally and characteristically involve a peculiar regard not just for

    ones own nation, but for the particular characteristics and merits and achievement of

    ones own nation. These latter are indeed values as merits and achievements and their

    character as merits and achievements provides reasons supportive of the patriots

    attitudes. But the patriot does not value in the same way precisely similar merits and

    achievements when they are the merits and achievements of some nation other than his or

    hers. For he or she at least in the role of patriot values them not just as merits and

    achievements, but as merits and achievements of this particular nation.

    To say this is to draw attention to the fact that patriotism is one of a class of

    loyalty-exhibiting virtues, other members of which are marital fidelity, the love of

    ones own family and kin, friendship, and loyalty to such institutions as schools and

  • 11

    cricket or baseball clubs. All these attitudes exhibit a peculiar action-generating regard

    for particular persons, institutions or groups, a regard founded upon a particular historical

    relationship of association between the person exhibiting the regard and the relevant

    person, institution or group. It is often, although not always, the case that associated with

    this regard will be a felt gratitude for the benefits which the individual takes him or

    herself to have received from the person, institution or group. But it would be one more

    mistake to suppose patriotism or other such attitudes of loyalty to be at their core or

    primarily responses of gratitude. For there are many persons, institutions, and groups to

    which each of us have good reason to feel grateful without this kind of loyalty being

    involved. What patriotism and such other attitudes involve is not just gratitude, but a

    particular kind of gratitude; and what those who treat patriotism and other such loyalties

    as virtues are committed to believing is not that what they owe their nation or whomever

    or whatever it is simply a requital for benefits received, based on some relationship of

    reciprocity of benefits.

    State University of New York

  • 12

    I.4 Michael Walzer, Spheres of Affection

    (excerpted from Michael Walzer, Spheres of Affection, Boston Review, Vol. 19, No. 5,

    1994)

    I am [not very] convinced by [Nussbaums] underlying and overriding world view

    perhaps because I am not a citizen of the world, as she would like me to be. I am not even

    aware that there is a world such that one could be a citizen of it. No one has ever offered

    me citizenship, or described the naturalization process, or enlisted me in the worlds

    institutional structures, or given me an account of its decision procedures (I hope that

    they are democratic), or provided me with a list of the benefits and obligations of

    citizenship, or shown me the worlds calendar and the common celebrations and

    commemorations of its citizens. I am wholly ignorant; and while a cosmopolitan

    education would be a very good thing, I dont see, from Nussbaums account, that it

    would teach me the things that any world citizen would need to know. It would, however,

    teach me things that American citizens need to know: why isnt that good enough? Cant

    I be a cosmopolitan American (along with all the other things that I am)? I have

    commitments beyond the borders of this or any other country, to fellow Jews, say, or to

    social democrats around the world, or to people in trouble in faraway countries, but these

    are not citizen-like commitments.

    Boston Review

  • 13

    I.5 Richard Rorty, Moral Universalism and Economic Triage

    (excerpted from Richard Rorty, Moral Universalism and Economic Triage, Unesco

    Philosophy Forum, online at http://www.unesco.org/phiweb/uk/2rpu/rort/rort.html)

    In what sort of situation might someone ask the question who are we?. It seems most

    appropriate in the mouth of someone trying to shape her audience into a more coherent

    community. It is the sort of rhetorical question a party leader might ask at a party rally. In

    such situations, it means something like what unifying ideal can we find to make us less

    like a mob and more like an army, less like people thrown together by accident and more

    like people who have united to accomplish a task?

    Who are we? is quite different from the traditional philosophical question what

    are we?. The latter is synonymous with Kants questions, What is Man?. Both mean

    something like how does the human species differ from the rest of the animal

    kingdom? or among the differences between us and the other animals, which ones

    matter most?. This what? question is scientific or metaphysical.

    By contrast, the who? question is political. It is asked by people who want to

    separate off the human beings who are better suited to some particular purpose than other

    human beings, and to gather the former into a self-conscious moral community: that is, a

    community united by reciprocal trust, and by willingness to come to fellow-members

    assistance when they need it. Answers to the who? question are attempts to forge, or

    reforge, a moral identity.

    Traditional moral universalism blends an answer to the scientific or metaphysical

    what? question with an answer to the political who? question. Universalism

    presupposes that the discovery of traits shared by all human beings suffices to show why,

    and perhaps how, all human beings should organize themselves into a cosmopolis. It

    proposes a scientific or metaphysical foundation for global politics. Following the model

    of religious claims that human beings are made in the image of God, philosophical

    universalism claims that the presence of common traits testifies to a common purpose. It

    says that the form of the ideal human community can be determined by reference to a

    universal human nature.

  • 14

    [T]he question who are we? should replace what are we? as the primordial

    question of philosophy. For it is the one to which we shall always return, the one which

    has already been answered when we answer other questions. Every account of what

    human beings are is a disguised proposal for shaping a new human community. The

    question who are we? replaces the Greek question What is Being? and also Kants

    questions What can I know? and What is Man?. It replaces all these with a new form

    of Kants question What may I hope?

    In this new form Kants question becomes what may we hope?. For it is no

    longer, as it was for Kant, a question about the immortality of the individual soul, but

    about the future of the species. The question who are we? is future-oriented in a way in

    which the question what are we? is not. The what? question enshrines the pre-

    Darwinian notion of a human essence, which has its place in a Platonic heaven of other

    essences. The who? question sets aside the notion of essence, of intrinsic reality... It

    thereby stops asking a timeless question, and asks a question about future time. But this

    question about the future is not a request for a prediction, but rather for a project. To ask

    who we are becomes a way of asking what future we should try, cooperatively, to build.

    [I]f you cannot render assistance to people in need, your claim that they form part

    of your moral community is empty. This in turn is an illustration of a more general,

    philosophical point: that it only makes sense to attribute a belief to someone if such an

    attribution helps one to predict the persons future actions. On this pragmatic account

    of belief, to believe that someone is one of us, a member of our moral community, is to

    exhibit readiness to come to their assistance when they are in need. To answer the

    question who are we? in a way that is relevant to moral questions is to pick out whom

    one is willing to do something to help. Pressing [this] point, I would argue that one is

    answering the question who are we? in a useful and informative way only if one

    thereby generates reliable predictions about what measures the group identified as we

    will take in specified circumstances.

    It follows that it is neither useful or informative to answer this question by

    reference to a class of people whom one has no idea how to help. Moral identification is

    empty when it is no longer tied to habits of action. That is why it is either hypocritical or

  • 15

    self-deceptive for the doctors to think of those who are left outside the hospital as us.

    It would be equally self-deceptive or hypocritical for those who do not believe that the

    industrialized democracies can bring either hope or human rights to the billions who lack

    both to use the term We, the people of the United Nations.

    I have been putting forward a philosophical argument that depends upon three

    premises. The first is that the primordial philosophical question is not what are we? but

    who are we?. The second is that who are we? means what community of reciprocal

    trust do we belong to?. The third is that reciprocal trust depends on feasibility as well as

    on good will. The conclusion I draw from these premises is that thinking of other people

    as part of the same we, depends not only on willingness to help those people but on

    belief that one is able to help them. In particular, answering the question who are we?

    with we are members of a moral community which encompasses the human species,

    depends on an ability to believe that we can avoid economic triage.

    Richard Rorty

  • 16

    I.6 Maurizio Viroli, For Love of Country

    (excerpted from the Epilogue to Maurizio Viroli, For Love of Country: An Essay on

    Patriotism and Nationalism, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995)

    Republican patriotism places the main emphasis on political participation. It was not

    primarily concerned with freedom in the modern sense of negative liberty and equal

    protection of individual rights, but with participatory self-rule. Political participation

    reinforces bonds of civic friendship, a sense of common history, and the feeling of

    belonging to a common political entity which constitutes the essence of patriotism.

    patriotism grows in a republic that allows for and encourages democratic self-

    government.

    All the theorists that have argued in favor of a patriotism based on the idea that to

    love ones country means to love the republic as a political community based on the

    principle of common liberty, with its own culture and way of life, are in fact indicating

    the possibility of a patriotism without nationalism. It is a patriotism that stresses that the

    citizens love can and must be obtained primarily by political means; that is, through the

    practice of good government and through justice. And by justice they mean the protection

    of civil rights and the political rights of citizens. To be loved by its citizens, the republic

    must not tolerate discrimination and privileges and must allow the citizens to participate

    in public life. To love the republic they must feel close to it; they must feel it as theirs,

    which means to feel their fellow-citizens dear, worthy of respect and compassion. The

    emphasis on citizenship is not only motivated by the argument that popular sovereignty

    guarantees that laws aim at the common good, but also that direct political participation

    reinforces attachment to the republic.

    As I have argued, patriotism of liberty does not need social, or cultural, or

    religious, or ethnic homogeneity. If the fatherland is less that a republic in the classical

    sense, citizens cannot be virtuous: they cannot love a state that treats them unjustly

    (though in fact they sometimes do). If the fatherland is more than a good republic if it is

    a good republic and a religious or cultural or social community civic virtue will

    probably reach its maximum. It may also, however, degenerate into the zealots love of

  • 17

    oneness, not the citizens political love. This implies that to see the right sort of

    patriotism grow, we need not strengthen homogeneity and oneness but work to strengthen

    the practice and the culture of citizenship.

    There seem to be two distinct, though partially overlapping, pathways to civic

    virtue: the path of homogeneity and that of liberty. Our way should be that of liberty; that

    is, a political way. We do not need more citizens attending national festivals with great

    fervour; nor do we need more citizens willing to offer their lives to protect their countrys

    religious or ethnic or cultural unity. We need, instead, more citizens willing and capable

    of mobilizing when one or more citizens are victims of injustice or discrimination, when

    unfair laws are passed or constitutional principles are violated.

    Patriotism is different from heroic self-abnegation. The former requires us to do

    something more than attending to our private business; the second demands the sacrifice

    of our personal concerns and even our life for the common good. The virtuous citizen

    goes to the public square or the meeting room when he or she has to, but then he or she

    goes back home, or to his shop, or to join his friends. The hero sacrifices all to the

    republic. His love of the republic is more than a political love; it is a love enhanced by

    religious identification or passion for glory. But republics, except for extraordinary

    circumstances need less than that; they need citizens who can practice civic virtue as a

    completion of private life and private interest.

    Clarendon Press

  • 18

    Questions and Exercises:

    I.

    1. (a) Provide a short definition of the concept of cosmopolitanism, as defined by

    Martha Nussbaum.

    (b) According to Nussbaum, ones place or community of birth are morally irrelevant

    characteristics. She later writes that The accident of where one is born is just that, an

    accident; any human being might have been born in any nation. Explain in what sense

    the community of ones birth is morally irrelevant.

    (c) Does the fact that something is an accident necessarily mean that that something is

    morally irrelevant?

    (d) Do you think that the characteristic which David Held identifies as central to his

    cultural cosmopolitanism the ability to stand outside of a singular location (the

    location of ones birth, land, upbringing, conversion), and to mediate traditions is

    something people should do and are capable of doing?

    2. (a) Point to distinctions between Nussbaums understanding of patriotism and

    MacIntyres.

    (b) In what way is ones love of country similar to ones love of family and friends?

    3. (a) What is Michael Walzers point?

    (b) Try to give a short account of what cosmopolitan citizenship would involve in

    terms of obligations toward the other citizens of the world.

    (c) Do you think that world citizenship is something that may be achieved today?

    4. (a) How does moral universalism, according to Richard Rorty, define the concept of a

    moral community? And how does Rorty understand this concept in the second part of

    the fragment?

    (b) In what way does Rortys argument resemble Walzers?

    (c) Rorty sums up his argument in the final paragraph by saying that in order to be able to

    think of other people as members of the same moral community (the same we), two

    conditions need to be satisfied. What are these two conditions, and is the second

    condition necessary?

  • 19

    (c) If Rorty is right about the first condition, is cosmopolitanism (world citizenship)

    possible today?

    5. (a) Define the patriotism of liberty.

    (b) To which of the previous notions of patriotism is that of Maurizio Viroli similar?

    II.

    1. Translate into Romanian the fragment by Michael Walzer.

    2. Translate into English the following text:

    Cosmopolitismul pe care ncerc s-l elogiez are puine lucruri n comun cu

    vechiul refren umanist despre cetenii lumii. Acel refren, legat de filozofia

    Luminilor, presupune optimism, credin n progres i, n definitiv, visul despre

    societatea universal, care nu mai sunt actuale: am sfrit prin a nva c nu

    este de ajuns s depeti sau s desfiinezi cteva frontiere pentru ca totul s

    mearg mai bine; noi frontiere, noi limite i noi excluderi sunt ntotdeauna pe

    punctul s se instaleze din nou, uneori chiar mai barbare dect cele vechi. Nu poi

    fi cetean al lumii dac trebuie s te smulgi tocmai din lume. Cosmopolitismul

    despre care vorbesc nu este nici vechea utopie despre o comunitate a tuturor

    oamenilor; ncepem s ne dm seama c nu exist o bun comunitate i c

    puinele experiene care, depind msurile comune, merit s fie trite nu sunt, la

    drept vorbind, umane.

    (Guy Scarpetta, Elogiu cosmopolitismului, Iai: Polirom, 1997)

  • 20

    II. POLITICAL LIBERALISM

    In its political version, modern liberalism was born out of the religious wars of the 17th

    century. John Locke, arguably the founding father of political liberalism, was the chief

    inspiration for the Declaration of Independence and, indeed, for its author, Thomas

    Jefferson. Jefferson was also a staunch advocate of the separation between the church and

    the state. The first fragment below is excerpted from his Notes on the State of Virginia.

    Jefferson is followed by Richard Rorty, who provides an updated version of

    political liberalism, situated somewhere between the author of the Declaration and John

    Rawls, probably the best known contemporary theorist of this political doctrine. In the

    third text, John Tomasi provides a more general account of modern political liberalism

    and of the way in which it differs from some versions of classical liberalism. The

    selection concludes with a small fragment by John Rawls himself.

  • 21

    II.1 Thomas Jefferson, Notes on the State of Virginia

    Along with the American Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson regarded the

    Statute of Virginia for Religious Freedom as one of his most important writings. As

    probably the least pious founder of the American republic, Jefferson was in great part

    responsible for the doctrine of the separation between state and church which, in the

    United States, is extremely strict. The Statute became a law in 1786, while Jefferson was

    serving as ambassador to France. While in Paris, he also oversaw the publication of

    another important work, Notes on Virginia (1785), in which he expresses similar views to

    those contained in the Statute, and from which the following fragment was extracted.

    (excerpted from Thomas Jefferson, Notes on the State of Virginia, Query XVII: The

    different religions received into that state)

    The error seems not sufficiently eradicated, that the operations of the mind, as well as the

    acts of the body, are subject to the coercion of the laws. But our rulers can have authority

    over such natural rights only as we have submitted to them. The rights of conscience we

    never submitted, we could not submit. We are answerable for them to our God. The

    legitimate powers of government extend to such acts only as are injurious to others. But it

    does me no injury for my neighbour to say there are twenty gods, or no god. It neither

    picks my pocket nor breaks my leg. If it be said, his testimony in a court of justice cannot

    be relied on, reject it then, and be the stigma on him. Constraint may make him worse by

    making him a hypocrite, but it will never make him a truer man. It may fix him

    obstinately in his errors, but will not cure them. Reason and free enquiry are the only

    effectual agents against error. Give a loose to them, they will support the true religion, by

    bringing every false one to their tribunal, to the test of their investigation. They are the

    natural enemies of error, and of error only. Had not the Roman government permitted

    free enquiry, Christianity could never have been introduced. Had not free enquiry been

    indulged, at the era of the reformation, the corruptions of Christianity could not have

    been purged away. If it be restrained now, the present corruptions will be protected, and

    new ones encouraged. Was the government to prescribe to us our medicine and diet, our

    bodies would be in such keeping as our souls are now. Thus in France the emetic was

    once forbidden as a medicine, and the potatoe as an article of food. Government is just as

  • 22

    infallible too when it fixes systems in physics. Galileo was sent to the inquisition for

    affirming that the earth was a sphere: the government had declared it to be as flat as a

    trencher, and Galileo was obliged to abjure his error. This error however at length

    prevailed, the earth became a globe, and Descartes declared it was whirled round its axis

    by a vortex. The government in which he lived was wise enough to see that this was no

    question of civil jurisdiction, or we should all have been involved by authority in

    vortices. Reason and experiment have been indulged, and error has fled before them.

    It is error alone which needs the support of government. Truth can stand by itself. Subject

    opinion to coercion: whom will you make your inquisitors? Fallible men; men governed

    by bad passions, by private as well as public reasons. And why subject it to coercion? To

    produce uniformity. But is uniformity of opinion desirable? No more than of face and

    stature. Introduce the bed of Procrustes then, and as there is danger that the large men

    may beat the small, make us all of a size, by lopping the former and stretching the latter.

    Difference of opinion is advantageous in religion. The several sects perform the office of

    a Censor morum over each other. Is uniformity attainable? Millions of innocent men,

    women, and children, since the introduction of Christianity, have been burnt, tortured,

    fined, imprisoned; yet we have not advanced one inch towards uniformity. What has been

    the effect of coercion? To make one half the world fools, and the other half hypocrites.

    To support roguery and error all over the earth. Let us reflect that it is inhabited by a

    thousand millions of people. That these profess probably a thousand different systems of

    religion. That ours is but one of that thousand. That if there be but one right, and ours that

    one, we should wish to see the 999 wandering sects gathered into the fold of truth. But

    against such a majority we cannot effect this by force. Reason and persuasion are the only

    practicable instruments. To make way for these, free enquiry must be indulged; and how

    can we wish others to indulge it while we refuse it ourselves. But every state, says an

    inquisitor, has established some religion. No two, say I, have established the same. Is this

    a proof of the infallibility of establishments? Our sister states of Pennsylvania and New

    York, however, have long subsisted without any establishment at all. The experiment was

    new and doubtful when they made it. It has answered beyond conception. They flourish

    infinitely. Religion is well supported; of various kinds, indeed, but all good enough; all

    sufficient to preserve peace and order: or if a sect arises, whose tenets would subvert

  • 23

    morals, good sense has fair play, and reasons and laughs it out of doors, without suffering

    the state to be troubled with it. They do not hang more malefactors than we do. They are

    not more disturbed with religious dissensions. On the contrary, their harmony is

    unparalleled, and can be ascribed to nothing but their unbounded tolerance, because there

    is no other circumstance in which they differ from every nation on earth. They have made

    the happy discovery, that the way to silence religious disputes, is to take no notice of

    them.

  • 24

    II.2 Richard Rorty, Religion as Conversation-stopper

    (excerpted from Richard Rorty, Religion as Conversation-stopper, in Rorty, Philosophy

    and Social Hope, Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1999)

    [The] inference from privatization [of religion] to trivialization [of religion] is invalid

    unless supplemented with the premise that the nonpolitical is always trivial. But this

    premise seems false. Our family and love lives are private, nonpolitical and nontrivial.

    The poems we atheists write, like the prayers our religious friends raise, are private,

    nonpolitical and nontrivial. Writing poems is, for many people, no mere hobby, even

    though they never show those poems to any save their intimates. The same goes for

    reading poems, and for lots of other private pursuits that both give meaning to individual

    human lives and are such that mature, public-spirited adults are quite right in not

    attempting to use them as a basis for politics. The search for private perfection, pursued

    by theists and atheists alike, is neither trivial nor, in a pluralistic democracy, relevant to

    public policy.

    Such exclusion, however, is at the heart of the Jeffersonian compromise, and it is

    hard to see what more just arrangement might take the place of that compromise.

    Contemporary liberal philosophers think that we shall not be able to keep a democratic

    political community going unless the religious believers remain willing to trade

    privatization for a guarantee of religious liberty

    The main reason religion needs to be privatized is that, in political discussion with

    those outside the relevant religious community, it is a conversation stopper.

    It is one thing to say that religious beliefs, or the lack of them, will influence

    political convictions. Of course they will. It is another thing to say that the public square

    should be open to religious argument, or that liberalism should develop a politics that

    accepts whatever form of dialogue a member of the public offers. What is a specifically

    religious form of dialogue, except perhaps a dialogue in which some members cite

    religious sources for their beliefs? What could a specifically religious argument be,

    except an argument whose premises are accepted by some because they believe that these

    premises express the will of God? I may accept those same premises for purely secular

  • 25

    reasons for example reasons having to do with the maximizing of human happiness.

    Does that make my argument a nonreligious one? Even if it is exactly the same argument

    made by my religious fellow citizen? Surely the fact that one of us gets his premises in

    church and the other in the library is, and should be, of no interest to our audience in the

    public square. The arguments that take place there, political arguments, are best thought

    of as neither religious nor nonreligious.

    The epistemology suitable for a democracy is one in which the only test of a

    political proposal is its ability to gain assent from people who retain radically diverse

    ideas about the point and meaning of human life, about the path to private perfection. The

    more such consensus becomes the test of a belief, the less important is the beliefs source.

    Richard Rorty

  • 26

    II.3 John Tomasi, Liberalism Beyond Justice

    (excerpted from Chapter One of John Tomasi, Liberalism Beyond Justice, Princeton, NJ:

    Princeton University Press, 2001)

    The liberal principle of legitimacy like each of the others reflects what its proponents

    believe is most important in human social life. For liberals, this is the idea that in the

    conditions of pluralism that mark modern societies, individual citizens must be

    recognized as the ultimate arbiters of what gives value to their own lives. Political power

    must be justifiable in principle to each of them. For liberals, the justification of social

    structures must be provided not in the unified terms of any single religious doctrine, story

    of nation, or all-encompassing economic theory. Rather, justification must proceed in

    terms of whatever questions citizens themselves think fit to ask. The liberal principle of

    legitimacy says that a system of social order is justified only if it is conducted on the

    basis of principles that citizens might be expected to endorse after asking their questions

    and considering the best answers the defenders of that social order might give.

    Political liberalism was born out of a crisis in this principle of legitimacy. The

    ambition underlying all versions of liberalism has long been to define the common good

    of political association in terms of a minimal moral conception that is, a basic value or

    set of values that most citizens share despite even their many important differences.

    Political principles are neutral and thus satisfy the liberal principle of legitimacy

    insofar as they can be justified by reference to such shared values, without assuming the

    validity or truth of any particular (controversial) conception of the good life.

    This liberal principle of legitimacy does not require that every person must agree

    with every particular rule, policy, or court decision that is enforced by the liberal state.

    Rather, the idea is that if many people agree to have some set of foundational principles

    regulate the basic structure of their society, including the processes by which particular

    policies and laws will be arrived at, then they affirm the use of political coercion even

    regarding the particular outcomes they dislike.

    In the seminal formulations of Kant and Mill, the liberal commitment to state

    neutrality was justified ultimately by reference to a particular view of human moral

  • 27

    nature one championing autonomy (for Kant, a life lived according to rational will) or

    individualism (for Mill, an experimental attitude toward ones projects). Both Kant and

    Mill, each for his own reasons and in his own way, affirmed the idea that the liberal state

    should not seek to impose any particular view of the good life on its citizens. Rather,

    these liberals argued that forms of life have their value to people because, and only when,

    individuals freely come to affirm those ways of life for themselves. However, many

    other liberal theorists have come to worry that even a broadened ideal of individualism is

    something on which people may reasonably disagree.

    On the traditional or comprehensive liberal approach the hope has been to

    defend some suitably general liberal view about true human moral nature against critics

    by means of philosophical argumentation. The critics having been confronted and their

    beliefs about human moral nature shown to be false, philosophers could then use their

    own true view of moral personality as a shared moral basis for liberal politics. But

    accepting the fact of reasonable value pluralism1 requires that liberals now abandon all

    such philosophical ambitions. In conditions of institutional freedom, convergence on a

    single conception of human moral nature is unlikely, no matter how long or cleverly

    philosophers argue. A new trailhead must be considered: perhaps liberals should begin

    looking for the shared moral basis for liberal politics merely in the cluster of moral ideas

    that people in Western democracies already hold, however inchoately, regarding their

    political lives.

    Political liberals thus propose two major adjustments to the traditional liberal

    paradigm. First, political liberals recast their arguments for state neutrality as arguments

    that appeal only to peoples beliefs about politics itself. Rawls sets aside questions

    about the truth of the (various) foundations of those shared public elements. He

    emphasizes instead the formative role of liberal institutions in leading otherwise diverse

    people to share a common set of political ideas central among them the shared idea that

    whatever their differences, all people in liberal societies should be respected as free and

    equal for political purposes. This first adjustment, a change in the way the liberal

    conception of justice is justified, is known as the politicization of justice. 1 The fact of reasonable value pluralism refers to the reality that in todays societies (and, as a matter of fact, in those of the past too), people differ with one another on a variety of beliefs and principles, which are apparently irreconcilable.

  • 28

    Princeton University Press

  • 29

    II.4 John Rawls, Political Liberalism

    (excerpted from Lecture I of John Rawls, Political Liberalism, New York: Columbia

    University Press, 1993)

    In formulating [a conception of justice independent of the opposing and conflicting

    philosophical and religious doctrines that citizens affirm], political liberalism applies the

    principle of toleration to philosophy itself. The religious doctrines that in previous

    centuries were the professed basis of society have gradually given way to principles of

    constitutional government that all citizens, whatever their religious view, can endorse.

    Comprehensive2 philosophical and moral doctrines likewise cannot be endorsed by

    citizens generally, and they also no longer can, if they ever could, serve as the professed

    basis of society.

    Political liberalism, then, aims for a political conception of justice as a

    freestanding view. It offers no specific metaphysical or epistemological doctrine beyond

    what is implied by the political conception itself. As an account of political values, a

    freestanding political conception does not deny there being other values that apply, say,

    to the personal, the familial, and the associational; nor does it say that political values are

    separate from, or discontinuous with, other values. Our aim is to specify the political

    domain and its conception of justice in such as way that its institutions can gain the

    support of an overlapping consensus [of the various comprehensive and other doctrines].

    In this case, citizens themselves, within the exercise of their liberty of thought and

    conscience, and looking to their comprehensive doctrines, view the political conception

    as derived from, or congruent with, or at least not in conflict with, their other values.

    Columbia University Press

    2 According to Rawls, a comprehensive doctrine (philosophical, religious, or otherwise) is one which provides us with answers about such ultimate matters as the meaning of life, or truth, or virtue, the human condition, etc.

  • 30

    Questions and Exercises:

    1. (a) Read the text by Thomas Jefferson and try to summarize his views of religion.

    Give at least four arguments why Jefferson thinks the state should not be involved with

    religion.

    2. (a) Provide a short summary of Richard Rortys argument about religion and politics.

    (b) What is the meaning of the phrase the Jeffersonian compromise?

    (c) What does Rorty mean when he says that in public political debate religion is a

    conversation-stopper?

    3. (a) Since the plurality of values makes it impossible, according to John Tomasi, to use

    the true view of moral personality as a shared moral basis for liberal politics, where

    should people look for much a moral ground?

    (b) Explain Tomasis idea of the politicization of justice.

    (c) What is the difference between classical liberalism (i.e. the comprehensive

    liberalism of Mill or Kant) and political liberalism?

    4. (a) What does American philosopher John Rawls mean by his definition of political

    liberalism as a doctrine which applies the principle of toleration to philosophy itself? In

    what sense does here philosophy resemble religion?

    (b) Why does Rawls say that a (liberal) political conception of justice needs to be

    freestanding? Freestanding from what?

    (c) What should, according to Rawls, be the relation between the citizens comprehensive

    doctrines and political liberalism?

    II.

    1. Translate into Romanian the fragment by John Rawls.

    2. Translate into English the following text:

    n opinia majoritii istoricilor gndirii politice, liberalismul, n varianta sa

    politic, s-a nscut n urma rzboaielor religioase din secolele XVI-XVII, ca o

    ncercare de rezolvare a celebrei probleme teologico-politice. A dori s subliniez

    aici n mod special anterioritatea liberalismului politic n raport cu cel economic;

    acesta din urm a aprut ulterior cristalizrii principiilor liberalismului politic.

  • 31

    Exist, ns, i un curent (mai recent) de interpretare, care afirm c nu se poate

    vorbi cu adevrat despre liberalism dect n secolul al XIX-lea, dup Revoluia

    francez, o dat cu trecerea la un liberalism de guvernmnt n Anglia sau Frana.

    Indiferent de interpretarea pe care o dm, este evident faptul c, la sfritul

    secolului al XVII-lea, tolerana statului n raport cu diferite doctrine religioase a

    fost singura cale de a impune pacea social unor comuniti divizate pn atunci

    de interminabile lupte intestine. Sfera de intervenie a statului a fost astfel limitat

    n baza unor reguli clar stabilite (de obicei, constituionale), n timp ce legile

    urmau s vegheze nu la pedepsirea ereticilor, ci la sigurana public a cetenilor.

    (Aurelian Criuu, A fi sau a nu fi liberal?, n Criuu, Elogiul libertii: Studii

    de filosofie politic, Iai: Polirom, 1998)

  • 32

    III. MODELS OF DEMOCRACY

    The following selection of texts starts with two classics. First, Montesquieu briefly

    discusses in a sub-chapter of his Spirit of Laws some of the advantages and disadvantages

    of small republics, large republics, and confederacies. Secondly, James Madison in his

    well-known Federalist 10 essay takes up roughly the same questions, only to provide

    what seems to be a different answer.

    As a good starting point for assessing the merits and demerits of the various forms

    of democratic association above, Robert Dahl offers five criteria according to which

    democracies can be tested. Both James Fishkin and Anthony King focus on one of these

    criteria in order the evaluate the state of current democracies, as well as possible options

    for enhancing democracy in the future.

    Finally, Benjamin Barber expresses his optimism with respect to the power of

    modern technologies to advance the cause of democracy, while Andrew Shapiro and Cass

    Sunstein provide us with several reasons to think twice.

  • 33

    III.1 Montequieu, The Spirit of Laws

    (excerpted from Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws, Book IX, 1)

    If a republic be small, it is destroyed by a foreign force; if it be large, it is ruined by an

    internal imperfection.

    To this twofold inconvenience democracies and aristocracies are equally liable,

    whether they be good or bad. The evil is in the very thing itself, and no form can redress

    it.

    It is, therefore, very probable that mankind would have been, at length, obliged to

    live constantly under the government of a single person, had they not contrived a kind of

    constitution that has all the internal advantages of a republican, together with the external

    force of a monarchical, government. I mean a confederate republic.

    This form of government is a convention by which several petty states agree to

    become members of a larger one, which they intend to establish. It is a kind of

    assemblage of societies, that constitute a new one, capable of increasing by means of

    further associations, till they arrive at such degree of power as to be able to provide for

    the security of the whole body.

    It was these associations that so long contributed to the prosperity of Greece. By

    these the Romans attacked the whole globe, and by these alone the whole globe

    withstood them; for when Rome had arrived at her highest pitch of grandeur, it was the

    associations beyond the Danube and the Rhine associations formed by the terror of her

    arms that enabled the barbarians to resist her.

    The associations of cities were formerly more necessary than in our times. A

    weak, defenseless town was exposed to greater danger. By conquest it was deprived not

    only of the executive and legislative powers, as at present, but moreover of all human

    property.

    A republic of this kind, able to withstand an external force, may support itself

    without any internal corruption; the form of this society prevents all manner of

    inconveniencies.

  • 34

    If a single member should attempt to usurp the supreme power, he could not be

    supposed to have an equal authority and credit in all the confederate states. Were he to

    have too great an influence over one, this would alarm the rest; were he to subdue a part,

    that which would still remain free might oppose him with forces independent of those

    which he had usurped, and overpower him before he could be settled in his usurpation.

    Should a popular insurrection happen in one of the confederate states, the others

    are able to quell it. Should abuses creep into one part, they are reformed by those that

    remain sound. The state may be destroyed on one side, and not on the other; the

    confederacy may be dissolved, and the confederates preserve their sovereignty.

    As this government is composed of petty republics, it enjoys the internal

    happiness of each; and with regard to its external situation, by means of the association, it

    possesses all the advantages of large monarchies.

  • 35

    III.2 James Madison, Federalist 10

    James Madison wrote this essay, originally published in the Federalist journal under the

    pseudonym Publius, at a time when Americans were trying to craft a constitution for

    the 13 colonies recently liberated from British rule. Americans were facing two options:

    that of building a confederate structure of powerful small states with a weaker central

    government (the anti-federalist position); and that of creating a federation of states with a

    more powerful central government and less power for the individual states (the federalist

    stance). Madison, who together with Alexander Hamilton and John Jay published in the

    Federalist periodical a number of essays later known as The Federalist Papers, supported

    the latter alternative. Not surprisingly, he was a knowledgeable reader of Montesquieu.

    (excerpted from James Madison, Federalist 10, The Federalis Papers)

    Among the numerous advantages promised by a well constructed union, none deserves to

    be more accurately developed than its tendency to break and control the violence of

    faction. The friend of popular governments, never finds himself so much alarmed for

    their character and fate, as when he contemplates their propensity to this dangerous vice.

    He will not fail therefore to set a due value on any plan which, without violating the

    principles to which he is attached, provides a proper cure for it. The instability, injustice

    and confusion introduced into the public councils, have in truth been the mortal diseases

    under which popular governments have everywhere perished; as they continue to be the

    favorite and fruitful topics from which the adversaries to liberty derive their most

    specious declamations. ...

    By a faction I understand a number of citizens, whether amounting to a majority

    or minority of the whole, who are united and actuated by some common impulse of

    passion, or of interest, adverse to the rights of other citizens, or to the permanent and

    aggregate interests of the community.

    There are two methods of curing the mischiefs of faction: The one, by removing

    its causes; the other, by controlling its effects.

    There are again two methods of removing the causes of faction: The one by

    destroying the liberty which is essential to its existence; the other, by giving to every

    citizen the same opinions, the same passions, and the same interests.

  • 36

    It could never be more truly said than of the first remedy, that it is worse than the

    disease. Liberty is to faction, what air is to fire, an aliment without which it instantly

    expires. But it could not be a less folly to abolish liberty, which is essential to political

    life, because it nourishes faction, than it would be to wish the annihilation of air, which is

    essential to animal life because it imparts to fire its destructive agency.

    The second expedient is as impracticable, as the first would be unwise. As long as

    the reason of man continues fallible, and he is at liberty to exercise it, different opinions

    will be formed. As long as the connection subsists between his reason and his self-love,

    his opinions and his passions will have a reciprocal influence on each other; and the

    former will be objects to which the latter will attach themselves. The diversity in the

    faculties of men from which the rights of property originate, is not less an insuperable

    obstacle to an uniformity of interests. The protection of these faculties is the first object

    of government. From the protection of different and unequal faculties of acquiring

    property, the possession of different degrees and kinds of property immediately results:

    And from the influence of these on the sentiments and views of the respective

    proprietors, ensues a division of the society into different interests and parties.

    The latent causes of faction are thus sown in the nature of man; and we see them

    everywhere brought into different degrees of activity, according to the different

    circumstances of civil society. A zeal for different opinions concerning religion,

    concerning government, and many other points, as well of speculation as of practice; an

    attachment to different leaders ambitiously contending for pre-eminence and power; or to

    persons of other descriptions whose fortunes have been interesting to the human passions,

    have in turn divided mankind into parties, inflamed them with mutual animosity, and

    rendered them much more disposed to vex and oppress each other, than to co-operate for

    their common good. So strong is this propensity of mankind to fall into mutual

    animosities, that where no substantial occasion presents itself, the most frivolous and

    fanciful distinctions have been sufficient to kindle their unfriendly passions, and excite

    their most violent conflicts. But the most common and durable source of factions, has

    been the various and unequal distribution of property. The regulation of these various

    and interfering interests forms the principal task of modern legislation, and involves the

    spirit of party and faction in the necessary and ordinary operations of government.

  • 37

    It is in vain to say, that enlightened statesmen will be able to adjust these clashing

    interests, and render them all subservient to the public good. Enlightened statesmen will

    not always be at the helm: Nor, in many cases, can such an adjustment be made at all,

    without taking into view indirect and remote considerations, which will rarely prevail

    over the immediate interest which one party may find in disregarding the rights of

    another, or the good of the whole.

    The inference to which we are brought, is, that the causes of faction cannot be

    removed; and that relief is only to be sought in the means of controlling its effects.

    If a faction consists of less than a majority, relief is supplied by the republican

    principle, which enables the majority to defeat its sinister views by regular vote: It may

    clog the administration, it may convulse the society; but it will be unable to execute and

    mask its violence under the forms of the constitution. When a majority is included in a

    faction, the form of popular government on the other hand enables it to sacrifice to its

    ruling passion or interest, both the public good and the rights of other citizens. To secure

    the public good, and private rights against the danger of such a faction, and at the same

    time to preserve the spirit and the form of popular government, is then the great object to

    which our enquiries are directed.

    By what means is this object attainable? Evidently by one of two only. Either the

    existence of the same passion or interest in a majority at the same time, must be

    prevented; or the majority, having such co-existent passion or interest, must be rendered,

    by their number and local situation, unable to concert and carry into effect schemes of

    oppression. If the impulse and the opportunity be suffered to coincide, we well know that

    neither moral nor religious motives can be relied on as an adequate control. They are not

    found to be such on the injustice and violence of individuals, and lose their efficacy in

    proportion to the number combined together; that is, in proportion as their efficacy

    becomes needful.

    From this view of the subject, it may be concluded that a pure democracy, by

    which I mean a society, consisting of a small number of citizens, who assemble and

    administer the government in person, can admit of no cure for the mischiefs of faction. A

    common passion or interest will, in almost every case, be felt by a majority of the whole;

    a communication and concert results from the form of government itself; and there is

  • 38

    nothing to check the inducements to sacrifice the weaker party, or an obnoxious

    individual. Hence it is, that such democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and

    contention; have ever been found incompatible with personal security, or the rights of

    property; and have in general been as short in their lives, as they have been violent in

    their deaths. Theoretic politicians, who have patronized this species of government, have

    erroneously supposed, that by reducing mankind to a perfect equality in their political

    rights, they would, at the same time, be perfectly equalized, and assimilated in their

    possessions, their opinions, and their passions.

    A republic, by which I mean a government in which the scheme of representation

    takes place, opens a different prospect, and promises the cure for which we are seeking.

    Let us examine the points in which it varies from pure democracy, and we shall

    comprehend both the nature of the cure, and the efficacy which it must derive from the

    union.

    The two great points of difference between a democracy and a republic, are first,

    the delegation of the government, in the latter, to a small number of citizens elected by

    the rest; secondly, the greater number of citizens, and greater sphere of country, over

    which the latter may be extended.

    The effect of the first difference is, on the one hand, to refine and enlarge the

    public views, by passing them through the medium of a chosen body of citizens, whose

    wisdom may best discern the true interest of their country, and whose patriotism and love

    of justice, will be least likely to sacrifice it to temporary or partial considerations. Under

    such a regulation, it may well happen that the public voice pronounced by the

    representatives of the people, will be more consonant to the public good, than if

    pronounced by the people themselves convened for the purpose. On the other hand, the

    effect may be inverted. Men of factious tempers, of local prejudices, or of sinister

    designs, may be intrigue, by corruption, or by other means, first obtain the suffrages, and

    then betray the interests of the people. The question resulting is, whether small or

    extensive republics are most favourable to the election of proper guardians of the public

    weal; and it is clearly decided in favour of the latter by two obvious considerations.

    In the first place it is to be remarked, that however small the republic may be, the

    representatives must be raised to a certain number, in order to guard against the cabals of

  • 39

    a few; and that however large it may be, they must be limited to a certain number, in

    order to guard against the confusion of a multitude. Hence the number of representatives

    in the two cases not being in proportion to that of the constituents, and being

    proportionally greatest in the small republic, it follows, that if the proportion of fit

    characters be not less in the large than in the small republic, the former will present a

    greater option, and consequently a greater probability of a fit choice.

    In the next place, as each representative will be chosen by a greater number of

    citizens in the large than in the small republic, it will be more difficult for unworthy

    candidates to practise with success the vicious arts, by which elections are too often

    carried; and the suffrages of the people being more free, will be more likely to centre on

    men who possess the most attractive merit, and the most diffusive and established

    characters.

    The other point of difference is, the greater number of citizens and extent of

    territory which may be brought within the compass of republican, than of democratic

    government; and it is this circumstance principally which renders factious combinations

    less to be dreaded in the former, than in the latter. The smaller the society, the fewer

    probably will be the distinct parties and interests composing it; the fewer the distinct

    parties and interests, the more frequently will a majority be found of the same party; and

    the smaller the number of individuals composing a majority, and the smaller the compass

    within which they are placed, the more easily will they concert and execute their plans of

    oppression. Extend the sphere, and you take in a greater variety of parties and interests;

    you make it less probable that a majority of the whole will have a common motive to

    invade the rights of other citizens; or if such a common motive exists, it will be more

    difficult for all who feel it to discover their own strength, and to act in unison with each

    other. Besides other impediments, it may be remarked, that where there is a

    consciousness of unjust or dishonourable purposes, communication is always checked by

    distrust, in proportion to the number whose concurrence is necessary.

    Hence it clearly appears, that the same advantage, which a republic has over a

    democracy, in controlling the effects of faction, is enjoyed by a large over a small

    republic is enjoyed by the union over the states composing it. Does this advantage

    consist in the substitution of representatives, whose enlightened views and virtuous

  • 40

    sentiments render them superior to local prejudices, and to schemes of injustice? It will

    not be denied, that the representation of the union will be most likely to possess these

    requisite endowments. Does it consist in the greater security afforded by a greater variety

    of parties, against the event of any one party being able to out-number and oppress the

    rest? In an equal degree does the increased variety of parties, comprised within the union,

    increase this security. Does it, in fine, consist in the greater obstacles opposed to the

    concert and accomplishment of the secret wishes of an unjust and interested majority?

    Here, again, the extent of the union gives it the most palpable advantage.

    The influence of factious leaders may kindle a flame within their particular states,

    but will be unable to spread a general conflagration through the other states: A religious

    sect, may degenerate into a political faction in a part of the confederacy; but the variety

    of sects dispersed over the entire face of it, must secure the national councils against any

    danger from that source: A rage for paper money, for an abolition of debts, for an equal

    division of property,3 or for any other improper or wicked project, will be less apt to

    pervade the whole body of the union, than a particular member of it; in the same

    proportion as such a malady is more likely to taint a particular county or district, than an

    entire state.

    In the extent and proper structure of the union, therefore, we behold a republican

    remedy for the diseases most incident to republican government. And according to the

    degree of pleasure and pride, we feel in being republicans, ought to be our zeal in

    cherishing the spirit, and supporting the character of federalists.

    3 These were all debates contemporary with Madison. Most were raised in the context of the American war of independence and its aftermath.

  • 41

    III.3 Robert Dahl, On Democracy

    (excerpted from Chapter 4 of Robert Dahl, On Democracy, New Haven and London:

    Yale University Press, 1998)

    Within the enormous and often impenetrable thicket of ideas about democracy, is it

    possible to identify some criteria that a process for governing an association would have

    to meet in order to satisfy the requirement that all the members are equally entitled to

    participate in the associations decisions about its policies? There are, I believe, at least

    five such standards.

    Effective participation. Before a policy is adopted by the association, all the

    members must have equal and effective opportunities for making their views known to

    the other members as to what the policy should be.

    Voting equality. When the moment arrives at which the decision about policy will

    finally be made, every member must have an equal and effective opportunity to vote, and

    all votes must be counted as equal.

    Enlightened understanding. Within reasonable limits as to time, each member

    must have equal and effective opportunities for learning about the relevant alternative

    policies and their likely consequences.

    Control of the agenda. The members must have the exclusive opportunity to

    decide how and, if they choose, what matters are to be placed on the agenda. Thus the

    democratic process required by the three preceding criteria is never closed. The policies

    of the association are always open to change by its members, if they so choose.

    Inclusion of adults. All, or at any rate most, adult permanent residents should have

    the full rights of citizens that are implied by the first four criteria. Before the twentieth

    century this criterion was unacceptable to most advocates of democracy.

    Yale University Press

  • 42

    III.4 James Fishkin, The Voice of the People

    (excerpted from the Introduction to James Fishkin, The Voice of the People: Public

    Opinion and Democracy, New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1995)

    There is a classic Jimmy Stewart movie, Magic Town, about Grandview, a small town

    in the Midwest that is a perfect statistical microcosm of the United States, a place where

    the citizens opinions match perfectly with polls of the entire nation. A pollster

    (Jimmy Stewart), secretly uses surveys from this mathematical miracle as a shortcut to

    predicting public opinion. Instead of collecting a national sample, he can more quickly

    and cheaply collect surveys from this single small town. The character played by Jane

    Wyman, a newspaper editor, finds out what is going on and publishes her discovery. As a

    result the national media descend upon the town, which becomes, overnight, the public

    opinion capital of the U.S. The citizens of Grandview become self-conscious because

    they are now the perfect barometer of national opinion. They begin to feel a heavy

    responsibility, knowing that what they say will be listened to throughout the world. They

    arrange to collect their own survey, The Official Grandview Poll, but with the proviso

    that reference libraries be provided at every polling booth. Because the issues are

    important, they believe people should be informed.

    With this new sense of responsibility, and their heightened interest in the issues,

    the townspeoples views soon diverge from those of the rest of the country. The climax

    comes when the town announces the result that 79 percent of them would be willing to

    vote for a woman for president! This is taken as such a preposterous departure from

    conventional opinion that they become a source of national ridicule.

    Yet which opinions are more worth listening to? The conventional opinion of the

    time, offered in response to questions from the Gallup poll, that people should not

    support a woman for president, or the very different view the citizens of Grandview

    finally came to, when they thought their opinions would actually matter, and after they

    had had a chance to reexamine their prejudices and preconceptions? Those considered

    judgments were, indeed, unrepresentative of the views of the rest of the country. But then

    again, the rest of the country had not really thought much about the question.

  • 43

    Obviously, public opinion polls of the standard kind give us a snapshot of what

    the country is actually thinking. They are a valuable means of telling both the country and

    its political leaders about the current state of mass opinion. For that purpose, the new

    opinions of the Grandview citizens became worthless, just as the Jimmy Stewart

    character had said they would, once word got out. But for other purposes, particularly for

    finding a public voice worth listening to, the final views of Grandview offer a useful

    supplement to the vagaries of an inattentive public. There is a kind of recommending

    force to the new opinions at Grandview: this is what a microcosm of the country thinks

    about an issue once it has had a better chance to focus on it, to discuss it, and to

    reexamine shared preconceptions. Perhaps this is what the entire country, not just the

    microcosm, would think about the issue if it focused on it in a more sustained way.

    Grandview symbolizes a central problem: when can a microcosm, or some other

    small part of the country, speak for the whole, speak for the entire citizenry and its

    interests?

    Accepting that there are many portions of the people who purport to speak for

    everyone, can we find conditions when all the people can speak without requiring

    surrogates, conditions where the whole can, in some sense, speak for itself? Even if we

    were to ask everyone what they thought about an issue, we would still be offering a

    representation, a picture, of public opinion. That opinion would have been formed under

    certain conditions, and those conditions may be far from favorable for the public being

    able to form a reasonable opinion, or even any coherent opinion at all. Representation

    comes from taking a part for the whole but it also comes from taking what the people

    seem to be saying at a snapshot in time under one set of conditions as a representation

    of what they really think. As we shall see, they may not really be thinking much at all.

    In a broad sense, there will always be conflicting representations of public opinion, but

    there will also be conditions, which we can distinguish, under which the voices of the

    people are more, or less, worth listening to.

    Conflicting representations of public opinion are inescapable. In spite of these

    conflicts, there is one simple answer to the question When can the people best speak for

    themselves? that runs through the history of democratic experimentation: The public

    can best speak for itself when it can gather together in some way to hear the arguments

  • 44

    on the various sides of an issue and then, after face-to-face discussion, come to a

    collective decision. The image of the New England town meeting or the Athenian

    Assembly provides a picture of people discussing things democratically in one place. It is

    the longstanding model for how to conduct democracy under conditions where not only

    does everyones vote count the same but social conditions have been provided that

    facilitate everyones thinking through the issues together. We can call this image the ideal

    of face-to-face democracy. A key issue in the continuing American experiment with

    democracy is: How can we adapt this ideal to the large-scale nation-state, to a population

    which cannot possibly gather together in the same room to take decisions?

    What happens to the vote when the ideal of face-to-face democracy no longer

    applies? What happens when we vote without the social conditions that encourage

    everyones gathering together in face-to-face discussion? Much of the continuing saga of

    the democratic idea can be thought of as an answer to that question. Voting in primaries

    or referendums, voting in general elections based on a sound bite of information or an

    impression culled from newspaper headlines, voting based on nothing more than name

    recognition or party label, or not voting at all (which has become the norm in the modern

    era) these phenomena are quite different from voting in a small group after extensive

    face-to-face discussion. The American Founders struggled to adapt the ideal of face-to-

    face democracy to the large nation-state. But they thought it could be accomplished only

    through a system of elected representation, where the representatives would have the

    discussions and deliberations and come to decisions on behalf of the rest of us. Others,

    particularly the opponents of the Constitution who have come to be known as the anti-

    Federalists, wanted to place the locus of decision closer to the people, even if, for many

    issues, the ideal of face-to-face discussion could not be implemented. The beginnings of

    referendum democracy are built into the conflicts that arose at the founding.

    Yale University Press

  • 45

    III.5 Anthony King, Running Scared

    (excerpted from Anthony King, Running Scared, The Atlantic Monthly, Vol. 279, No.

    1, January 1997)

    Numerous opinion polls show that millions of Americans are profoundly dissatisfied with

    the functioning of their political system. Consequently, there is a widespread disposition

    in the United States at all levels of society, from the grass roots to the editorial

    conference and the company boardroom to want to make American democracy work

    better, and concrete proposals abound for achieving this goal.

    The proposed reforms can be grouped loosely under four headings. First come

    those that if implemented would amount to the creation of electronic town meetings,

    taking advantage of technological developments such as CD-ROM, interactive cable

    systems, electronic mail, and the Internet. The Wall Street Journal referred in this general

    connection to arranging a marriage of de Tocqueville and technology.

    Second, and related, are proposals for promoting democratic deliberation and

    citizen participation. The Kettering Foundation and the Public Agenda Foundation

    already organize National Issues Forums that embrace some 3,000 educational and civic

    groups across America. David Mathews, the president of the Kettering Foundation,

    considers these modern forums to be directly linked to Americas ancient town meeting

    tradition. Benjamin R. Barber, a political philosopher at Rutgers University, would go

    further and create a nationwide network of neighborhood assemblies that could take

    actual decisions on strictly local matters and also debate and lobby on broader national

    questions. James S. Fishkin, a political scientist at the University of Texas, likewise seeks

    to leap the modern barriers to face-to-face democracy by means of what he calls

    deliberative opinion polls (which have been tried, with considerable success, in

    England).

    The third group of proposed reforms is equally radical but more old-fashioned.

    This group seeks to complete the work of Progressive Era reformers4 by extending to the

    4 The progressive era is a period in US history, roughly extending between 1900 and the end of World War I, in which a large number of initiatives political (e.g. right to vote for women,

  • 46

    federal level the characteristic state-level reforms that were introduced in that period: the

    referendum, the initiative, and the recall.5 The political analyst Kevin Phillips, for

    example, suggests that the United States should propose and ratify an amendment to the

    Constitution setting up a mechanism for holding nationwide referendums to permit the

    citizenry to supplant Congress and the president in making certain categories of national

    decisions. He would also like to see congressmen and senators be subject to popular

    recall once they have been in office for a year.

    Finally, many commentators and the majority of the American public strongly

    back the newest and most fashionable item on the making democracy work better

    agenda: the imposition of term limits on both state and federal elected officials, notably

    members of Congress. But the great majority of those who favor term limits, true to the

    American democratic tradition, are less concerned with good government and the public

    interest as such than with the present generation of politicians alleged lack of

    responsiveness to the mass of ordinary people. At the center of this argument is the idea

    that the United States is now governed by an unresponsive, self-perpetuating, and

    increasingly remote class of professional politicians, a class that ought to be replaced as

    soon as possible by citizen legislators men and women who will serve the people

    simply because they are the people. As one advocate of term limits puts it, ordinary

    people the proposed citizen legislators of the future know things about life in

    America that people who have lived as very self-important figures in Washington for

    thirty years have no way of knowing or have forgotten.

    Some of the items on this four-part shopping list of reforms are intrinsically

    attractive, or at least a good case can be made for them. Nevertheless, taken as a whole,

    the mainstream reformist agenda, with its traditional American emphasis on agency

    democracy and its view of politicians as mere servants of the peoples will, rests on

    extremely tenuous conceptual foundations and, more important, is almost certainly

    direct election of the US senators), democratic (see following note), social (e.g. improved living conditions and education for the poor, better infrastructure), and economic (e.g. regulation of working conditions, safety measures, busting of monopolies) radically changed the face of American society. 5 These progressive reforms refer, respectively, to the right to sanction some public policies by means of a referendum, the right to advance proposals for public policies, and the right to discharge public officials before their term expires.

  • 47

    inappropriate as a response to the practical needs of turn-of-the-century America.

    Ame